Quotes

"Dialogue is mutual search for a new reality, not debate to win with stronger arguments. In a dialogue propositions are pointers toward a common new reality; not against each other to win a verbal battle, but complementing each other in an effort to accommodate legitimate goals of all parties, inspired by theories and values, and constructive-creative-concrete enough to become a causa finalis". Galtuung


"I use the concept of affect as away of talking about a margin of manouverability, the 'where we might be able to go' and 'what we might be able to do' in every present situation. I guess 'affect' is a word I use for 'hope': Massumi


"A discourse is a system of words, actions, rules, beliefs, and institutions that share common values. Particular discourses sustain particular worldviews. We might even think of a discourse as a worldview in action. Discourses tend to be invisible--taken for granted as part of the fabric of reality."Fairclough


Emergence is “the principle that entities exhibit properties which are meaningful only when attributed to the whole, not to its parts.” Checkland


"What the designer cares about is whether the user perceives that some action is possible (or in the case of perceived non-affordances, not possible)." Norman




Sunday 20 June 2010

Constructivism : Gains, B.R.

For example, Quillian‘s (1967) citation of Kelly (1955) in his seminal paper on semantic networks, and Kelly‘s emphasis that ―no construct ever stands entirely alone; it makes sense only as it appears in a network‖ (p.304), situate him in the origins of semantic network models of human memory and reasoning. These models were formalized through the theory of description logics (Baader, Calvanese, McGuinness, Nardi and Patel- Schneider, 2003), as tractable sub-sets of first-order logics, where it also emerged that general negation is a fundamental source of intractable complexity in reasoning. Kelly‘s emphasis on dichotomous opposition within a range of convenience, rather than general negation leads to a substructural logic (Koslow, 1992) that resolves the tractability problem, but his contribution has long been forgotten in the semantic network
literature.
Similarly, Frake (1969) acknowledges Kelly (1955) as the source of his notion of contrast sets that has not only became a foundational model in cognitive anthropology but was also adopted by Kuhn in his theory of conceptual change in scientific revolutions as a solution to

revolutions as a solution to Wittgenstein‘s problem of open texture in family resemblance (Andersen, 2000). Kelly‘s role is again forgotten in the derivative
literature.
The reconstruction of Kelly‘s theoretical psychology within a modern framework is both of historic interest and also a potentially significant contribution to some of the current major issues in computational logic, cognitive science, psychology of science, and psychology of
reasoning.
The paper, Visualizing logical aspects of conceptual structures, which Fay asked me to précis for this newsletter is one of a series deriving from this reconstructive research, none of which are central to it, but all of which are by-products that emerge when I am asked to contribute to a special issue or volume on any topic. It was prepared for a special issue of the Journal of Visual Languages and Computing on visual languages for logic. The paper derives the mathematical relations between representations of conceptual structures, including Euler diagrams (Euler, Brewster and Griscom, 1840), conceptual grids (Kelly, 1955), semantic networks (Quillian, 1967), conceptual spaces (Gärdenfors, 2000) and logical symbolism (Baader et al., 2003). It proves the formal equivalence of these diverse representations, translating between what are apparently quite different approaches to modeling representation and reasoning processes, using Kelly‘s integration of the logic of ―opposition‖ and ―ordination‖ and its representation as a ―conceptual grid‖ to provide a ―cybernetic model‖ of the
―geometry of psychological space.‖
It does this using another notion from Kelly, that constructs may be used to construe other constructs. The self-
description of a construct network using

as features of each pole the implied fit of other poles when the first pole is asserted to fit an experience generates a conceptual grid, and the principal components analysis of this grid generates a geometric model of the original network. The paper shows that the network, grid, logical and geometric models are equivalent and one can move freely between them. The mathematical equivalence, however, does not imply psychological equivalence. The various models are complementary constructive alternatives providing different insights into the construct
systems they represent.
The paper also illustrates Kelly‘s assertion that a construct network supports anticipation by providing templets that can be fitted to experience, enabling present experience to be compared with past experiences. The abductive assumption that similar past experiences can be used to more fully represent present current experience allows additional aspects of
that experience to be hypothesized.
The most recent volume of Margolis‘ (2010) epic series of books on American philosophy recounts the triumph of Dewey‘s pragmatism and constructivism as a synthesis of analytic and continental philosophy, and, in doing so, incidentally provides philosophical foundations for PCP. Kelly‘s achievement of extracting the essence of Dewey‘s notion that human psychology is characterized by our anticipation of the future, ruthlessly excising all associated notions, such as learning, motivation and affect, as deriving from this, and formulating this as a rigorous theoretical psychology and a powerful applied psychology, is a significant contribution to this triumph. Kelly operationalized Dewey‘s ideas to provide the foundations for his own clinical psychology but, in doing so, he also provided a comprehensive rigorous model of pragmatic constructivism that others are only now beginning to rediscover.
Apple have popularized the use of the prefix ―i‖ to indicate associations with ―individual,‖ ―inform,‖ ―inspire‖ and
―internet‖ and these terms seem also to be the appropriate associations for the modern reconstruction of Kelly‘s
mathematical psychology—hence the title of this note. I believe he would have found it both interesting and amusing, the
stimulus for yet another limerick, to see
how his work is being reformulated in this information age.

References
The paper summarized and associated papers are available at http://
cpsc.ucalgary.ca/~gaines/reports
Andersen, H. (2000). Kuhn's account of family resemblance: a solution to the problem of wide-open texture. Erkenntnis 52, 313-337.
Baader, F., Calvanese, D., McGuinness, D., Nardi, D. and Patel-Schneider, P., eds. (2003). The Description Logic Handbook. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

Euler, L., Brewster, D. and Griscom, J. (1840). Letters of Euler on Different Subjects in Natural Philosophy. Harper, New York.
Frake, C. O. (1969). The ethnographic study of cognitive systems. In Cognitive Anthropology Tyler, S. A., ed, pp. 28-41. Holt, New York,.
Gärdenfors, P. (2000). Conceptual Spaces: The Geometry of Thought. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
Kelly, G. A. (1955). The Psychology of Personal Constructs. New York, Norton
Koslow, A. (1992). A Structuralist Theory of Logic. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Margolis, J. (2010). Pragmatism's Advantage: American and European Philosophy at the End of the Twentieth Century. Stanford University Press, Stanford, CA.
Quillian, M. R. (1967). Word concepts: a theory and simulation of some basic semantic capabilities. Behavioral Science 12, 410-430.

No comments:

Post a Comment